Logic
Contents
5. Logic¶
In today’s lecture we shall review the basics of mathematical logic. The traditional mathematical view of logic is that, together with set theory, logic provides a foundation upon which mathematics is built. It is thus natural to expect there to be just one foundation, for what would be the purpose of having several?
We shall remain true to the title of this course and deviate from the mathematical stance by slanting heavily toward the computer science perspective, which takes logic to be a tool for accomplishing various engineering tasks (no worries, you will not be required to use a hammer).
There are many different kinds of logic that we cannot properly address in a single lecture. We shall only look at basic kinds of logic today:
the propositional logic, which consists of atomic propositions, the constants
, and the logical connectives , , .the predicate logic enriches the propositional calculus with predicates, relations and the quantifiers
and .
Logics are presented in different styles, depending on how the basic reasoning laws are formulated and how proofs are constructed:
Hilbert system: the connectives are governed by axioms; proofs are sequences of statements.
Natural deduction: the connectives and the quantifiers are governed by inference rules; proofs are well-founded trees, generated inductively by the inference rules.
Sequent calculus: looks similar to natural deduction, because it also has inference rules and deduction trees. On closer inspection one notices important differences, such as multi-part conclusions and built-in symmetries that are not present in natural deduction.
Our presentation is in the natural deduction style, because it most closely resembles type theory. The resemblance is not at all accidental.
From traditional propositional and predicate logic many other kinds of logic have arisen, such as:
Modal logic in which there are modal operators which express the mode of truth. For example,
might mean something like “ is true in all states of the system that can be reached from the current state”.Linear logic in which every hypothesis must be used exactly once. Such logics are used to model situations in which we need to keep track of how many times each resource (a variable, a hypothesis) has been accessed.
Temporal logic is logic equipped with operators for expressing future and past truth values. For example,
might mean “ will be the case” (at some future time, or in every future time).
Such non-standard logics are used in computer science to specify, model, and reason about communication protocols, software correctness, hardware designs, etc.
{-# OPTIONS --overlapping-instances #-}
open import Data.List using (List; []; _∷_; [_]; _++_; foldr)
module 05-logic where
5.1. Propositional logic¶
In the first lecture we spoke about inference rules, which we use now to specify the reasoning principle of the propositional logic.
5.1.1. Propositional formulas¶
The formulae of the propositional calculus are built inductively from:
a set of atomic formulas,
the constants false
and true ,the connectives conjunction
, disjunction , and implication .
In Agda the formulae form an algebraic datatype:
module PropositionalLogic (AtomicFormula : Set) where
infixr 6 _∧_
infixr 5 _∨_
infixr 4 _⇒_
data Formula : Set where
`_ : AtomicFormula → Formula -- atomic formula
⊤ : Formula -- truth (unicode \top)
⊥ : Formula -- falsehood (unicode \bot)
_∧_ : Formula → Formula → Formula -- conjunction (unicode \wedge)
_∨_ : Formula → Formula → Formula -- disjunction (unicode \vee)
_⇒_ : Formula → Formula → Formula -- implication (unicode \=>)
We usually denote formulas with lower-case letters
equivalence
is short-hand for ,negation
is short-hand for .
infix 3 _⇔_
infix 7 ¬_
_⇔_ : Formula → Formula → Formula
ϕ ⇔ ψ = (ϕ ⇒ ψ) ∧ (ψ ⇒ ϕ)
¬_ : Formula → Formula
¬ ϕ = ϕ ⇒ ⊥
The basic judgement form of propositional calculus is
which is read as “the hypotheses
5.1.2. Inference rules¶
Inference rules tell us which judgements are derivable.
There are three kinds of inference rules:
structural rules for general manipulation of judgements
each connective has introduction and elimination rules
other special rules, such as excluded middle (which we do not include by default)
Let us begin to spell these out in Agda. The hypotheses are a list of formulas.
Hypotheses = List Formula
The predicate _∈_
expresses membership in a list:
infix 3 _∈_
data _∈_ {A : Set} : A → List A → Set where
instance
∈-here : {x : A} → {xs : List A} → x ∈ (x ∷ xs)
∈-there : {x y : A} {xs : List A} → {{x ∈ xs}} → x ∈ (y ∷ xs)
The keyword instance
tells Agda that it should automatically use the constructors
∈-here
and ∈-there
when trying to find an instance argument (see the rule hyp
below
which has such an argument).
See also
Read the documentation on instance arguments.
Next come the rules of inference. (The long dashed lines are comments, inserted to make the syntax similar to inference rules.)
infixl 2 _⊢_ -- unicode \vdash
data _⊢_ : (Δ : Hypotheses) → (φ : Formula) → Set where
The structural rules for manipulation of hypotheses:
weaken : {Δ₁ Δ₂ : Hypotheses}
→ (φ : Formula)
→ {ψ : Formula}
→ Δ₁ ++ Δ₂ ⊢ ψ
-----------------------
→ Δ₁ ++ [ φ ] ++ Δ₂ ⊢ ψ
contract : {Δ₁ Δ₂ : Hypotheses}
→ (φ : Formula)
→ {ψ : Formula}
→ Δ₁ ++ [ φ ] ++ [ φ ] ++ Δ₂ ⊢ ψ
--------------------------------
→ Δ₁ ++ [ φ ] ++ Δ₂ ⊢ ψ
exchange : {Δ₁ Δ₂ : Hypotheses}
→ (φ₁ φ₂ : Formula)
→ {ψ : Formula}
→ Δ₁ ++ [ φ₁ ] ++ [ φ₂ ] ++ Δ₂ ⊢ ψ
-----------------------------------------
→ Δ₁ ++ [ φ₂ ] ++ [ φ₁ ] ++ Δ₂ ⊢ ψ
Exercise
Explain the structural rules in your own words.
The remaining structural rule states that a hypothesis entails itself:
hyp : {Δ : Hypotheses}
→ (φ : Formula)
→ {{φ ∈ Δ}}
-----------------
→ Δ ⊢ φ
Note that we used the double braces {{⋯}}
which stand for an instance
argument. Agda can automagically derive these from given instances. This
way we are saved from manually writing proofs that witness list membership.
The connective for the logical constants are special in the sense that one only has an introduction rule and the other only an elimination rule.
⊤-intro : {Δ : Hypotheses}
------------------
→ Δ ⊢ ⊤
⊥-elim : {Δ : Hypotheses}
→ {φ : Formula}
→ Δ ⊢ ⊥
-------------------
→ Δ ⊢ φ
Conjunction has both kinds of rules:
∧-intro : {Δ : Hypotheses}
→ {φ ψ : Formula}
→ Δ ⊢ φ
→ Δ ⊢ ψ
-------------------
→ Δ ⊢ φ ∧ ψ
∧-elim₁ : {Δ : Hypotheses}
→ {φ ψ : Formula}
→ Δ ⊢ φ ∧ ψ
-------------------
→ Δ ⊢ φ
∧-elim₂ : {Δ : Hypotheses}
→ {φ ψ : Formula}
→ Δ ⊢ φ ∧ ψ
-------------------
→ Δ ⊢ ψ
Disjunction and implication follow a similar pattern:
∨-intro₁ : {Δ : Hypotheses}
→ {φ ψ : Formula}
→ Δ ⊢ φ
------------------
→ Δ ⊢ φ ∨ ψ
∨-intro₂ : {Δ : Hypotheses}
→ {φ ψ : Formula}
→ Δ ⊢ ψ
-------------------
→ Δ ⊢ φ ∨ ψ
∨-elim : {Δ : Hypotheses}
→ {φ₁ φ₂ ψ : Formula}
→ Δ ⊢ φ₁ ∨ φ₂
→ Δ ++ [ φ₁ ] ⊢ ψ
→ Δ ++ [ φ₂ ] ⊢ ψ
---------------------
→ Δ ⊢ ψ
⇒-intro : {Δ : Hypotheses}
→ {φ ψ : Formula}
→ Δ ++ [ φ ] ⊢ ψ
--------------------
→ Δ ⊢ φ ⇒ ψ
⇒-elim : {Δ : Hypotheses}
→ {φ ψ : Formula}
→ Δ ⊢ φ ⇒ ψ
→ Δ ⊢ φ
-------------------
→ Δ ⊢ ψ
For comparison, here is how one writes the inference rules for disjunction and implication on the walls of a cave:
Example
We demonstrate how derivations are built by proving that
example₁ : (A B C : Formula) → [] ⊢ (A ∨ B ⇒ C) ⇔ (A ⇒ C) ∧ (B ⇒ C)
example₁ A B C =
∧-intro
(⇒-intro
(∧-intro
(⇒-intro
(⇒-elim
(hyp (A ∨ B ⇒ C))
(∨-intro₁ (hyp A))
)
)
(⇒-intro
(⇒-elim
(hyp (A ∨ B ⇒ C))
(∨-intro₂ (hyp B))
)
)
)
)
(⇒-intro
(⇒-intro
(∨-elim
(hyp (A ∨ B))
(⇒-elim
(∧-elim₁
(hyp ((A ⇒ C) ∧ (B ⇒ C)))
)
(hyp A)
)
(⇒-elim
(∧-elim₂
(hyp ((A ⇒ C) ∧ (B ⇒ C)))
)
(hyp B)
)
)
)
)
Example
The following somewhat silly example derives hyp
.
(You should uncomment example₄₂
)
-- example₄₂ : (A B C : Formula) → A ∷ B ∧ C ∷ A ∷ [] ⊢ B ∧ (A ∧ ⊤)
-- example₄₂ A B C = ∧-intro (∧-elim₁ (hyp (B ∧ C))) (∧-intro (hyp A) ⊤-intro)
Notice that hyp A
above makes Agda unhappy because it sees that there are two ways of
proving that A
is a hypothesis. We can avoid the complaints by telling Agda which A
we
want by instantiating the instance argument of hyp
explicitly:
example₁₂ : (A B C : Formula) → A ∷ B ∧ C ∷ A ∷ [] ⊢ B ∧ (A ∧ ⊤)
example₁₂ A B C = ∧-intro (∧-elim₁ (hyp (B ∧ C))) (∧-intro (hyp A {{∈-here}}) ⊤-intro)
example₁₃ : (A B C : Formula) → A ∷ B ∧ C ∷ A ∷ [] ⊢ B ∧ (A ∧ ⊤)
example₁₃ A B C = ∧-intro (∧-elim₁ (hyp (B ∧ C))) (∧-intro (hyp A {{∈-there {{∈-there {{∈-here}}}}}}) ⊤-intro)
If we think of ∈-here
as “zero” and ∈-there
as “successor” then the elements of ϕ ∈ Δ
are seen to be the position at which ϕ
appears in the list Δ
.
5.1.3. Derivable and admissible rules¶
Once the basic inference rules are given, we can combine them to get new ones. There are two ways of doing this, known as derivable and admissible rules.
Example
From the premise ϕ ∧ ψ
we may conclude ψ ∧ ϕ
:
∧-commute : {Δ : Hypotheses}
→ {ϕ ψ : Formula}
→ Δ ⊢ ϕ ∧ ψ
-------------------
→ Δ ⊢ ψ ∧ ϕ
∧-commute p =
∧-intro
(∧-elim₂ p)
(∧-elim₁ p)
The proof of ∧-commute
just packages up a combination of rules to give a derivation of
the conclusion from the premise, without inspecting the derivation p
of the premise.
Definition (Derivable rule)
A rule of inference hyp
), and its conclusion is the conclusion of
You will derive more rules in the exercises.
Some rules cannot be established with such simple “template derivations” and require us to actually inspect the derivations of the premises and transform them into derivations of the conclusion by a recursive procedure. These are known as admissible rules.
Definition (Admissible rule)
An inference rule is admissible when all of its instances satisfy the property: if the premises are derivable then the conclusion is derivable.
Example
The inference rule
is admissible. To see this, we must transform a derivation hyp (ϕ ∧ ψ)
with ∧-intro (hyp ϕ) (hyp ψ)
.
Remark: If we are allowed to use cut
or implications, the the rule is actually
derivable (exercise).
In general it is advantageous to have few basic rules of inference, because that makes the logic easier to study. As it turns out, weakening, contraction, and exchange are redundant in the sense that they are admissible.
For instance, to see that weakening is admissible, consider a derivation
5.1.4. The difference between ⊢
and ⇒
¶
Almost every student of logic asks themselves at some point what is the difference between
entailment
Indeed we can, but
The learned way to explain the difference is that entailment
The cut rule¶
Let us continue the comparison between entailment and implication. The cut rule
is a structural rule of natural deduction. We can read it as follows: “Under hypothesis
We have not included the cut rule because it is derivable with the help of
5.1.5. Excluded middle¶
Our predicate calculus is intuitionistic. To get the classical calculus, we would also have to include the law of excluded middle:
There are many applications of logic in computer science where excluded middle is invalid, so we prefer to adopt it only when the situation calls for it. (This is a typical engineering attitude, which should be contrasted with the notion that logic is about truth, and that there is just one truth.)
Excluded middle is inter-derivable with double negation elimination:
Exercise
Derive double-negation elimination from excluded middle, and vice versa.
5.1.6. Truth tables¶
Semantics is an interpretation of a formal system in a (suitable kind of) mathematical structure. You are already familiar with one kind of semantics of propositional logic, namely the truth table semantics.
Let
which takes a mapping
The truth table of
Definition (Tautology)
A propositional formula
We say that a formula
The relationship between derivability in the propositional calculus and validity for truth-table semantics is captured by the following two theorems.
Theorem (Soundness of propositional calculus)
If the propositional calculus derives
Theorem (Completeness of classical propositional calculus)
If
Other kinds of logic also have soundness and completeness theorems with respect to their semantics. For example, the intuitionistic propositional calculus is sound and complete for Heyting algebras.
Soundness tells us that we may safely use a formal system of deduction to establish truth
about mathematical structures. For instance, rather than checking the truth table for
Completeness tells us that there is a goodness-of-fit between logic and semantics, in the sense that the logic can derive all truths. This is a particularly pleasing situation.
Sometimes we are given a mathematical structure of interest, for instance one describing the transitions of a finite-state system or a communication protocol, and the task is to devise a logic for reasoning about it. Soundness guarantees that the logic only proves true statements. Completeness may not easily be achievable for a single mathematical structure of interest.
5.2. Predicate logic¶
Predicate logic, also known as first-order logic, arises from the propositional logic when atomic formulas are replaced with predicates and relations. There are several steps, let us explain them carefully. We focus on single-sorted logic for simplicity.
5.2.1. Signatures¶
The language of a first-order theory is described by a signature, which consists of:
a list of function symbols
each of which has an arity ,a list of relation symbols
each of which has an arity .
Example
The signature for Peano arithmetic consists of:
function symbols:
of arity of arity of arity of arity
there are no relation symbols
5.2.2. Terms¶
A variable context is a list of distinct variables
The terms in context
each variable
is a term in ,if
is a function symbol of arity and are terms in context then so is .
A term is closed if it is a valid formula in the empty variable context.
Example
In context
We use the following syntactic sugar:
for , for , for , for .
5.2.3. Formulas¶
Given a variable context
the logical constants
and are formulasthe primitive formulas are:
for any terms and in context for any relation symbol of arity and terms in context
if
and are formulas in context then so are , , and .if
is a formula in context then and are formulas in context . The variable is bound by and .
A formula is closed if it is a valid formula in the empty variable context.
5.2.4. Hypothetical judgements¶
The basic judgement form is
where
5.2.5. Rules of inference¶
The rules of inference are those of propositional logic, adapted to the above judgement form, as well as the rules for equality and the quantifiers.
Equality¶
For terms
For terms
Universal quantifier¶
In the above rules, it is assumed that
Existential quantifier¶
In the above rules, it is assumed that
5.2.6. Specific rules¶
There is a (possibly empty) set of additional specific rules that a first-order theory may posses.
Example
The specific rules of Peano arithmetic are as follows.
For terms
For each formula